Evolution and the illusion of randomness

Elemente der Naturwissenschaft 96, 2012, P. 56-75 | DOI: 10.18756/edn.96.56

Abstract:

Most of us learned in school that all the beauty, embodied wisdom, and diversity of life on earth have resulted from two driving forces: random variation (genetic mutation) and selection of the fittest organisms. It is recognized today that mutations are, in general, far from random — and are appearing less so with almost every new discovery at the molecular level. But there remains one crucial respect, foundational to current evolutionary theory, in which mutations must continue to be deemed random: they must be random with respect to fitness. In other words, the likelihood of a mutation must be independent of its usefulness to the organism. This assumption underlies remarks by evolutionist Richard Dawkins and philosopher Daniel Dennett to the effect that evolution is an essentially blind, mindless, purposeless, and meaningless process. Yet the current literature powerfully testifies to the fact that (1) mutational processes in general participate in the highly organized and coordinated life processes of the cell and organism — so much so that some researchers now refer to “natural genetic engineering”; and (2) the idea of fitness, which biologists and philosophers have struggled with for decades, remains hopelessly obscure, and its obscurity is widely acknowledged. The claim of meaninglessness is therefore grounded in the wholly unsupported notion that mutations — which in general do not happen blindly at all, but are part of coherent life processes — are random at least when considered relative to a concept (fitness) that cannot be given any coherent or agreed-upon meaning.

References
  • Allen, J. A. (1988). Frequency-Dependent Selection by Predators. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, Part B, Biology vol. 319, pp. 485-503.
  • Ariew, André and R. C. Lewontin (2004). The Confusions of Fitness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science vol. 55, pp. 347-363.
  • Barbaric, Ivana, Gaynor Miller and T. Neil Dear (2007a). Appearances Can Be Deceiving: Phenotypes of Knockout Mice. Briefings in Functional Genomics and Proteomics vol. 6, no. 2, pp. 91-103. doi:10.1093/bfgp/ elm008
  • Beatty, John (1984). Chance and Natural Selection. Philosophy of Science vol. 51, no. 2 (June), pp. 183-211.
  • Beatty, John (1992). Fitness: Theoretical Contexts. In: Keywords in Evolutionary Biology, edited by Evelyn Fox Keller and Elisabeth A. Lloyd. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Bethell, Tom (1976). Darwin’s Mistake. Harpers Magazine vol. 252 (Feb.), pp. 70-75.
  • Bouchard, Frédéric and Alex Rosenberg (2004). Fitness, Probability and the Principles of Natural Selection. British Society for the Philosophy of Science vol. 55, pp. 693-712.
  • Brady, Ronald H. (1979). Natural Selection and the Criteria by Which a Theory Is Judged. Systematic Biology vol. 28, pp. 600-21.
  • Brady, Ronald H. (1982). Dogma and Doubt. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society vol. 17, pp. 79-96. Available at http://natureinstitute. org/txt/rb/dogma/dogmadoubt.htm.
  • Bridges, B. A. (1969). Mechanisms of Radiation Mutagenesis in Cellular and Subcellular Systems. Annual Review of Nuclear Science vol. 19, pp. 139-78.
  • Cook, Norman D. (1977). The Case for Reverse Translation. Journal of Theoretical Biology vol. 64, pp. 113-35.
  • Dawkins, Richard (1996). Climbing Mount Improbable. New York. W. W. Norton.
  • Dawkins, Richard (2006a). The Blind Watchmaker: Why the Evidence of Evolution Reveals a Universe Without Design. New York: W. W. Norton. First edition published in 1996.
  • Dawkins, Richard (2006b). The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Originally published in 1976.
  • Dennett, Daniel (1995a). Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. New York: Simon and Schuster.
  • Dennett, Daniel (1995b). Abstract of Evolution as Algorithm. In: The Mind, the Brain and Complex Adaptive Systems, edited by Harold Morowitz and Jerome Singer, Santa Fe Institute Studies in the Sciences of Complexity, Proceedings, vol. 22, pp. 221-3. Boston: Addison-Wesley. Abstract available at http://ase.tufts.edu/cogstud/papers/evolinsu.htm.
  • Elespuru, R. K. and K. Sankaranarayanan (2006). New Approaches to Assessing the Effects of Mutagenic Agents on the Integrity of the Human Genome. Mutation Research vol. 616, pp. 83-9. doi:10.1016/j. mrfmmm.2006.11.015
  • Gould, Stephen Jay (1976). This View of Life: Darwin’s Untimely Burial. Natural History vol. 85, pp. 24-30.
  • Graur, Dan (2008). Single-Base Mutation. Wiley Online Library, eLS. doi:10.1002/9780470015902.a0005093.pub2
  • Henry, Richard Conn (2005). The Mental Universe. Nature vol. 436, p. 29 (July 7). doi:10.1038/436029a
  • Holdrege, Craig (2005). The Giraffe’s Long Neck: From Evolutionary Fable to Whole Organism. Nature Institute Perspectives no. 4. Available at http://natureinstitute.org/pub/persp.
  • Lewontin, Richard C. (1978). Adaptation. Scientific American vol. 239, no. 3 (Sep.), pp. 212-30.
  • Lewontin, Richard. C. (1983). Gene, Organism, and Environment In: Evolution: From Molecules to Men, edited by D. S. Bendall. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press. Reprinted in Oyama, Griffiths and Gray 2001, pp. 59-66.
  • Lewontin, Richard C. (2001). Gene, Organism and Environment: A New Introduction. In Oyama, Griffiths and Gray (2001), pp. 55-7.
  • Matthen, Mohan and André Ariew (2005). How to Understand Causal Relations in Natural Selection: Reply to Rosenberg and Bouchard. Biology and Philosophy vol. 20, pp. 355-64. doi:10.1007/s10539-0055589-1
  • Mills, Susan K. and John H. Beatty (1979). The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness. Philosophy of Science vol. 46, no. 2 (June), pp. 263-86.
  • Millstein, Roberta L. and Robert A. Skipper Jr. (2007). Population Genetics. In: The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology, edited by David L. Hull and Michael Ruse. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.
  • Oyama, Susan, Paul E. Griffiths and Russell D. Gray, editors (2001). Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
  • Page, Scott L. and R. Scott Hawley (2003). Chromosome Choreography: The Meiotic Ballet. Science vol. 301 (Aug. 8) pp. 785-9. doi:10.1126/ science.1086605
  • Ruse, Michael (1984). Untitled (review of Philip Kitcher’s Abusing Science: The Case Against Creationism). Philosophy of Science vol. 51, no. 2 (June), pp. 348-54.
  • Sapienza, Carmen (2010). Selection Does Operate Primarily on Genes. In: Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology, edited by Francisco J. Ayala and Robert Arp. Malden MA: Wiley-Blackwell.