Performance and Participation in Scientific Experimentation

An Exploration of Human Thinking as Mental Action, from Scientific Experimentation to Systematic Thought Experiments
Elemente der Naturwissenschaft 119, 2023, P. 5-35 | DOI: 10.18756/edn.119.5

Abstract:

Experimentation is at the core of the natural sciences. Experiments are done for different reasons. They differ substantially from observations, where naturally occurring processes are taken note of or measured. Experiments instantiate the specific conditions that are necessary for isolating an experimental setting from its environment and manipulating the course of events in some way. This paper focuses on the role of human thinking as a mental action in the process of experimentation. In many cases, human action, in particular mental action, is taken for granted during experimentation, and the analysis tends to focus on questions of causality, the type of instruments and materials used, etc. This paper proposes to broaden the focus in the analysis of scientific experimentation, by taking mental actions into consideration: first by considering thought experiments, then pure thought experiments, and eventually what we might call (pure) experiments in thinking. Thinking is something that all human beings are capable of and, therefore, one can explore it systematically oneself. This paper outlines what the opportunities for such first-person experimentation are and how they can contribute to the enquiry of scientific experimentation.

References
  • Allchin, D. (2001): Error Types. Perspectives on Science 9(1), pp. 38–58.
  • Anderson, F. (2016): The Dynamic Phenomenology of Occurrent Thinking. Phenomenology and Mind 10, pp. 196–205.
  • Anderson,F.(2018):TheDynamicPhenomenologyofConscious,Occurrent Thinking: A First-Person Approach. United Kingdom.
  • Antonini, S., Mariotti, M.A. (2008): Indirect proof: What is specific to this way of proving? ZDM Mathematics Education 40(3), pp. 401–412.
  • Bandura, A. (2006): Toward a Psychology of Human Agency. Perspectives on Psychological Science 1(2), pp. 164–180.
  • Bayne, T., Montague, M. (2011): Cognitive Phenomenology: An Introduction. In: Bayne, T., Montague, M. (Eds.): Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford, pp. 1–34.
  • Brentano, F. (1973): Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt (O. Kraus, Ed.). Hamburg.
  • Breyer, T., Gutland, C. (2016a): Introduction. In: Breyer, T., Gutland, C. (Eds.): Phenomenology of Thinking. Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. New York, pp. 1–24.
  • Breyer, T., Gutland, C. (2016b): Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. New York.
  • Brown, J.R. (2004): Peeking into Plato’s Heaven. Philosophy of Science 71(5), pp. 1126–1138.
  • Buchwald, J.Z. (1998): Issues for the history of experimentation. In: Heidelberger, M., Steinle, F. (Eds.): Experimental Essays – Versuche zum Experiment. Baden-Baden, pp. 374–391.
  • Buckareff, A.A. (2005): How (Not) to Think About Mental Action. Philosophical Explorations 8(1), pp. 83–89.
  • Buzzoni, M. (2008): Thought Experiment in the Natural Sciences. Würzburg.
  • Buzzoni, M. (2011): On Mathematical Thought Experiments. Epistemologia 34, pp. 61–88.
  • Carrier, M. (1998): New experimentalism and the changing significance of experiments: On the shortcomings of an equipment-centered guide to history. In: Heidelberger, M., Steinle, F. (Eds.): Experimental Essays – Versuche zum Experiment. Baden-Baden, pp. 175–191.
  • Chisholm, R.M. (2011): Human freedom and the self. In: Feinberg, J., Shafer-Landau, R. (Eds.): Reason and Responsibility. Readings in Some Basic Problems of Philosophy. Boston MA, pp. 430–437.
  • Chudnoff, E. (2015): Cognitive Phenomenology. New York.
  • Comte, A. (1880): Einleitung in die positive Philosophie (Introduction to Positive Philosophy). Cours de philosophie positive, translated by Georg Heinrich Schneider. Leipzig.
  • Dingler, H. (1928): Das Experiment – Sein Wesen und seine Geschichte. München.
  • Duhem, P. (1998): Ziel und Struktur der physikalischen Theorien. Hamburg.
  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2016): Reductio ad absurdum from a dialogical perspective. Philosophical Studies 173(10), pp. 2605–2628.
  • Fehige, Y., Wiltsche, H. (2013): The Body, Thought Experiments, and Phenomenology. In: Frappier, M., Meynell, L., Brown, J.R. (Eds.): Thought Experiments in Science, Philosophy, and the Arts. London, pp. 69–89.
  • Fichte, J.G. (1997): Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre als Handschrift für seine Zuhörer. Introduction and register by W.G. Jacobs, Ed.; 4th ed. Hamburg.
  • Froese, T., Gallagher, S. (2010): Phenomenology and Artificial Life: Toward a Technological Supplementation of Phenomenological Methodology. Husserl Studies 26(2), pp. 83–106.
  • Gallagher, S. (2012): Multiple Aspects in the Sense of Agency. New Ideas in Psychology 30, pp. 15–31.
  • Gallagher, S., Zahavi, D. (2013): The Phenomenological Mind. 2nd ed. Hoboken.
  • Glymour, C. (2004): We believe in freedom of the will so that we can learn. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27(05), pp. 661–662.
  • Gooding, D. (1990): Experiment and the making of meaning: Human agency in scientific observation and experiment. Dordrecht.
  • Gooding, D. (1992a): Putting agency back into experiment. In: Pickering, A. (Ed.): Science as Practice and Culture. Chicago-London, pp. 65–112.
  • Gooding, D. (1992b): The Procedural Turn; or, Why Do Thought Experiments Work? In: Giere, R., Feigl, H. (Eds.): Cognitive Models of Science. Minneapolis, pp. 45–76.
  • Gooding, D. (1992c): What is Experimental About Thought Experiments? PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 280–290.
  • Gooding, D., Pinch, T., Schaffer, S. (1989): The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences. Cambridge UK.
  • Guillot, M. (2016): Thinking of Oneself as the Thinker: The Concept of Self and the Phenomenology of Intellection. Philosophical Explorations 19(2), pp. 138–160.
  • Gutland, C. (2021): Psychological Consciousness of Non-psychological Contents: Aspects of a Phenomenology of Sensations and Thoughts. European Psychologist 26(2), pp. 73–84.
  • Hacking, I. (1983): Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge UK.
  • Hacking, I. (1992): The self-vindication of the laboratory sciences. In: Pickering, A. (Ed.): Science as Practice and Culture. Chicago, London, pp. 29–64.
  • Heidelberger, M. (1998): Die Erweiterung der Wirklichkeit im Experiment. In: Heidelberger, M., Steinle, F. (Eds.): Experimental Essays – Versuche zum Experiment. Baden-Baden, pp. 71–92.
  • Heidelberger, M. (2003): Theory-Ladenness and Scientific Instruments in Experimentation. In: Radder, H. (Ed.): The Philosophy of Scientific Experimentation. Pittsburgh, pp. 138–151.
  • Heidelberger, M. (2009): Das Experiment in den Wissenschaften. In: Bartels, A., Stöckler, M. (Eds.): Wissenschaftstheorie. Ein Studienbuch. 2nd ed. Paderborn, pp. 155–176.
  • Heidelberger, M., Steinle, F. (Eds.) (1998): Experimental Essays – Versuche zum Experiment. Baden-Baden.
  • Hon, G. (1998): If this be error: Probing experiment with error. In: Heidelberger, M., Steinle, F. (Eds.): Experimental Essays – Versuche zum Experiment. Baden-Baden, pp. 227–248.
  • Hopp, W. (2014): Experiments in Thought. Perspectives on Science 22(2), pp. 242–263.
  • Janich, P. (1998): Was macht experimentelle Resultate empiriehaltig? Die methodisch-kulturalistische Theorie des Experimentes. In: Heidelberger, M., Steinle, F. (Eds.): Experimental Essays – Versuche zum Experiment. Baden-Baden, pp. 93–112.
  • Janich, P. (2016): Experiment und Menschenbild. In: Zeyer, K. (Ed.): Hugo Dingler (1881–1954): Philosophie und Theorie des Experimentes. Regensburg, pp. 13–26.
  • Jansen, J. (2016): Kant’s and Husserl’s Agentive and Proprietary Accounts of Cognitive Phenomenology. Philosophical Explorations 19(2), pp. 161–172.
  • Jorba, M., Moran, D. (2016): Conscious Thinking and Cognitive Phenomenology: Topics, Views and Future Developments. Philosophical Explorations 19(2), pp. 95–113.
  • Jorba, M., Vicente, A. (2014): Cognitive Phenomenology, Access to Contents, and Inner Speech. Journal of Consciousness Studies 21 (9–10), pp. 74–99.
  • Klemm, W.R. (2010): Free will debates: Simple experiments are not so simple. Advances in Cognitive Psychology 6, pp. 47–65.
  • Knobe, J., Buckwalter, W., Nichols, S., Robbins, P., Sarkissian, H., Sommers, T. (2012): Experimental philosophy. Annual Review of Psychology 63, pp. 81–99.
  • Knobe, J., Nichols, S. (2017): Experimental Philosophy. In: Zalta, E.N. (Ed.): The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017). Metaphysics Research Lab. Stanford.
  • Lange, R. (2003): Technology as Basis and Object of Experimental Practices. In: Radder, H. (Ed.): The Philosophy of Scientific Experimentation. Pittsburgh, pp. 119–137.
  • Lenhard, J. (2018): Thought experiments and simulation experiments. In: Stuart, M.T., Fehige, Y.J.H., Brown, J.R. (Eds.): The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. London, pp. 484–497.
  • Ludwig, K. (2007): The Epistemology of Thought Experiments: First Person Versus Third Person Approaches. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31(1), pp. 128–159.
  • Ludwig, K. (2018): Thought experiments and experimental philosophy. In: Stuart, M.T., Fehige, Y.J.H., Brown, J.R. (Eds.): The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. London, pp. 385–405.
  • Mangan, B. (2001): Sensation’s Ghost: The Nonsensory Fringe of Consciousness. PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research on Consciousness 7(18), pp. 1–44.
  • Mele, A. (1997): Agency and Mental Action. Philosophical Perspectives 11, pp. 231–249.
  • Mele, A. (2002): Goal-Directed Action: Teleological Explanations, Causal Theories, and Deviance. Noûs 34(14), pp. 279–300.
  • Montague, M. (2016): Cognitive Phenomenology and Conscious Thought. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 15(2), pp. 167–181.
  • Nado, J. (2016): Experimental Philosophy 2.0. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 5(3), pp. 159–168.
  • Nersessian, N.J. (2018): Cognitive science, mental modeling, and thought experiments. In: Stuart, M.T., Fehige, Y.J.H., Brown, J.R. (Eds.): The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. London, pp. 309–326.
  • O’Brien, L., Soteriou, M. (Eds.). (2009): Mental Actions. Oxford.
  • Petitmengin, C., Bitpol, M. (2009): The Validity of First-Person Descriptions as Authenticity and Coherence. Journal of Consciousness Studies 16(10–12), pp. 363–404.
  • Pitt, D. (2004): The Phenomenology of Cognition or What Is It Like to Think That P? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69(1), pp. 1–36.
  • Primas, H. (1991): Necessary and sufficient conditions for an individual description of the measurement process. In: Lahti, P., Mittelstaedt, P. (Eds.): Symposium on the foundations of modern physics, Joensuu, Finland 1990. Singapore, pp. 332–346.
  • Proust, J. (2001): A Plea for Mental Acts. Synthese 129(1), pp. 105–128.
  • Proust, J. (2009): Is there a Sense of Agency for Thought? In: O’Brien, L., Soteriou, M. (Eds.): Mental Actions. Oxford, pp. 253–280.
  • Putnam, H. (1973): Meaning and Reference. Journal of Philosophy 70(19), pp. 699–711.
  • Putnam, H. (1975): The Meaning of “Meaning”. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7, pp. 131–193.
  • Radder, H. (1998): Issus for a well-developed philosophy of scientific experimentation. In: Heidelberger, M., Steinle, F. (Eds.): Experimental Essays – Versuche zum Experiment. Baden-Baden, pp. 392–404.
  • Radder, H. (Ed.) (2003): The Philosophy of Scientific Experimentation. Pittsburgh.
  • Radder, H. (2009): The philosophy of scientific experimentation: A review. Automated Experimentation 1(2).
  • Schickore, J. (2005): “Through thousands of errors we reach the truth” – but how? On the epistemic roles of error in scientific practice. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36(3), pp. 539–556.
  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2008): The Unreliability of Naive Introspection. Philosophical Review 117(2), pp. 245–273.
  • Slagter, H.A., Davidson, R.J., Lutz, A. (2011): Mental Training as a Tool in the Neuroscientific Study of Brain and Cognitive Plasticity. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 5, 17.
  • Slagter, H.A., Lutz, A., Greischar, L.L., Francis, A.D., Nieuwenhuis, S., Davis, J.M., Davidson, R.J. (2007): Mental training affects distribution of limited brain resources. PLoS Biology 5(6), e138.
  • Sorensen, R.A. (1992): Thought experiments. New York.
  • Sosa, E. (2007): Experimental Philosophy and Philosophical Intuition. Philosophical Studies 132(1), pp. 99–107.
  • Soteriou, M. (2009): Mental Agency, Conscious Thinking, and Phenomenal Character. In: O’Brien, L., Soteriou, M. (Eds.): Mental Actions. Oxford, pp. 231–252.
  • Spener, M. (2011): Disagreement about cognitive phenomenology. In: Bayne, T., Montague, M. (Eds.): Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford, pp. 268–284.
  • Starikova, I., Giaquinto, M. (2018): Thought experiments in mathematics. In: Stuart, M.T., Fehige, Y.J.H., Brown, J.R. (Eds.): The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. London, pp. 257–278.
  • Steiner, R. (1918): Die Philosophie der Freiheit (The Philosophy of Spiritual Activity). 2nd ed. Berlin; 17th ed., Dornach 2021, GA 4.
  • Steinle, F. (1997): Entering New Fields: Exploratory Uses of Experimentation. Philosophy of Science 64, pp. S65–S74.
  • Steinle, F. (1998): Exploratives vs. Theoriebestimmtes Experimentieren: Ampères erste Arbeiten zum Elektromagnetismus. In: Heidelberger, M., Steinle, F. (Eds.): Experimental Essays – Versuche zum Experiment. Baden-Baden, pp. 272–297.
  • Steinle, F. (2005): Explorative Experimente. Ampère, Faraday und die Ursprünge der Elektrodynamik. Stuttgart.
  • Stich, S., Tobia, K. (2018): Intuition and its critics. In: Stuart, M.T., Fehige, Y.J.H., Brown, J.R. (Eds.): The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. London, pp. 369–384.
  • Stuart, M.T., Fehige, Y., Brown, J.R. (2018): Thought Experiments: State of the Art. In: Stuart, M.T., Fehige, Y.J.H., Brown, J.R. (Eds.): The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. London, pp. 1–28.
  • Tetens, H. (1987): Experimentelle Erfahrung. Hamburg.
  • Tye, M., Wright, B. (2011): Is There a Phenomenology of Thought? In: Bayne, T., Montague, M. (Eds.): Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford, pp. 285–325.
  • Weger, U., Wagemann, J. (2015a): The behavioral, experiential and conceptual dimensions of psychological phenomena: Body, soul and spirit. New Ideas in Psychology 39, pp. 23–33.
  • Weger, U., Wagemann, J. (2015b): The Challenges and Opportunities of First-Person Inquiry in Experimental Psychology. New Ideas in Psychology 36, pp. 38–49.
  • Weger, U., Wagemann, J., Meyer, A. (2018): Researching Mind Wandering from a First-Person Perspective. Applied Cognitive Psychology 32(3), pp. 298–306.
  • Wiltsche, H.A. (2018): Phenomenology and thought experiments. In: Stuart, M.T., Fehige, Y.J.H., Brown, J.R. (Eds.): The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. London, pp. 342–365.
  • Wright, G.H. von (1971): Explanation and Understanding. Ithaca.
  • Ziegler R. (2003): Teil II: Exploratives Experimentieren, ideales Experiment und konditionaler Determinismus. Elemente d. N. 79, pp. 22–50.
  • Ziegler, R., Weger, U. (2018): First-Person Experiments in Thinking. European Psychologist 23(3), pp. 189–205.
  • Ziegler, R., Weger, U. (2019): Exploring Conceptual Thinking and Pure Concepts from a First Person Perspective. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 18(5), pp. 947–972.
  • Ziegler, R., Weger, U. (2023): Thinking Action as a Performative and Participative Mental Awareness. Frontiers in Psychology – Consciousness Research 14:901678. DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2023.901678