Karl Popper als Hüter der Wissenschaftlichkeit – und warum er nicht immer Recht hat

Elemente der Naturwissenschaft 121, 2024, P. 46-60 | DOI: 10.18756/edn.121.46

Abstract:

Karl Popper (1902–1994) promoted the idealistic claim of dynamically advancing scientific progress through the recognition of the preliminary nature of all knowledge. For him, the application of the falsifying method was the criterion for the demarcation of the empirical sciences from dogmatic systems whose validity is based on subjective convictions. According to Popper, theories that refer to processes that can be experienced but not reproduced – such as Darwin’s theory of evolution – cannot contribute to the acquisition of objective scientific knowledge. Nevertheless, the explanatory value of this theory for the most diverse empirically verifiable findings is so great that no competing theory has been able to establish itself to date. Moreover, it enables predictions that – although highly improbable – lead to successful results. These examples show that falsification as the sole criterion of demarcation against pseudoscientific approaches excludes other acknowledged and indispensable scientific methods such as a systematic culture of observation and the concise description of singular events, and in this respect can justifiably be criticised.

References
  • Brestowsky, M. (2009): Evolution – ein Forschungsfeld im Grenzbereich. Naturwissenschaftliche Rundschau 62(1), S. 16–19.
  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2016): Popper’s philosophy of science: Looking ahead. Cambridge Companion to Karl Popper.
  • Hecht, J. (2013): Fossil hunting’s golden age. New Scientist 217(2904), S. 34–38.
  • Jablonka, E., Raz, G. (2009): Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance: prevalence, mechanisms, and implications for the study of heredity and evolution. The Quarterly Review of Biology 84(2), S. 131–176.
  • Jansson, J.K., Prosser, J.I. (2013): The life beneath our feet. Nature 494, S. 40–41.
  • Koonin, E.V., Wolf, Y.I. (2009): Is evolution darwinian or/and lamarckian? Biology direct 4/42.
  • Lakatos, I. (1970): Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge 4, S. 91–195.
  • Maxwell, G. (1974): Corroboration without demarcation. The Philosophy of Karl Popper 1, S. 292–321.
  • Mayr, E. (1984): Die Entwicklung der biologischen Gedankenwelt: Vielfalt, Evolution und Vererbung.
  • Mayr, E. (1989): Die darwinsche Revolution und die Widerstände gegen die Selektionstheorie. Naturwissenschaftliche Rundschau 7(42), S. 255–265.
  • Mayr, E. (2005): Konzepte der Biologie. Stuttgart.
  • Popper, K. (1965): Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge.
  • Popper, K. (1971): Logik der Forschung. 4. verbesserte Auflage, Tübigen.
  • Popper, K. (1978): Natural selection and the emergence of mind. Dialectica 32(3–4), S. 339–355.
  • Schilpp, P.A. (Hg) (1974): The philosophy of Karl Popper. LaSalle, Illinois.
  • West-Eberhard, M.J. (2003): Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford.
  • Windelband, W. (1894): Geschichte und Naturwissenschaft. Rede zum Antritt des Rektorats der Kaiser-Wilhelms-Universität Strassburg.